This website uses cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. Learn more

PPE Notes Wittgenstein Notes

Child Rules Rule Following Notes

Updated Child Rules Rule Following Notes

Wittgenstein Notes

Wittgenstein

Approximately 96 pages

Notes on Wittgenstein's later writings on meaning, language, rules and philosophy of mind, together with extensive notes on secondary literature, including Russell, Kripke, Child, Blackburn and Baker & Hacker....

The following is a more accessible plain text extract of the PDF sample above, taken from our Wittgenstein Notes. Due to the challenges of extracting text from PDFs, it will have odd formatting:

William Child - Wittgenstein

Chapter Five - The later philosophy: intentionality and rule-following

2. Rules and Rule-Following

  • Wittgenstein’s discussion of rules is influenced by:

    • his refutation of the imagist view of thought - in fact, any picture can be interpreted in numerous different ways, hence what a picture represents is not intrinsic but a matter of application

    • his family resemblance theory - our grasp of e.g. ‘game’ depends on the contingent fact that, having been introduced to the word in various examples, we find it natural to apply it in new cases in the same way

  • Wittgenstein considers two kinds of questions about rules:

    • constitutive questions: what makes it the case that the correct continuation of the series ‘+2’ is ‘1000, 1002, 1004, 1006’, and not ‘1000, 1004, 1008, 1012’? (accord with the rule)

    • questions bout our knowledge/grasp of rules: what makes it the case that I have grasped the rule for adding 2? How do I know what I have to do at each successive step in order to follow the rule?

i. The constitutive question

  • Philosophers have tended to answer the constitutive question in two ways:

    • Platonism: it is an absolutely objective fact that the correct continuation of the series ‘2, 4, 6...996, 998’ is ‘1000, 1002’ etc, and likewise with applying descriptive words - it is an absolutely objective fact that someone who has been trained in the normal way to use the word ‘red’ is using it correctly when applied to ripe tomatoes. This is because the continuation is (absolutely) the simplest or most natural,

      • Wittgenstein rejects Platonism:

        • first - there are evidently indefinitely many possible ways of continuing a series; if we point to something and say ‘this is called “Boo”’, the word ‘Boo’ might have 10,000 meanings, none of which is absolutely correct/simplest/most natural

        • second - we cannot justify the claim that our way of continuing is absolutely the correct one. if someone continues the series ‘1000, 1004, 1008’ then he is not going on in the same way by our standards, but clearly he is judged by his standards

          • we cannot show that our standards are absolutely correct

        • third - the idea of an absolutely correct continuation makes no sense. it is not that we can’t tell whether our way is correct; rather there is no such thing as an absolutely correct continuation - there are no further facts behind what is most natural by our standards

    • Constructivism: the correct application of a rule is determined by what we (would) take to be correct when we (if we were to) consider the case and reach a verdict - the fact that we find it natural to continue the series (in normal circumstances at least) by putting ‘1002, 1004, 1006’ makes that the correct continuation. Normative claims about correct continuation are underpinned by (but do not mean the same as) empirical claims about how people actually continue.

      • two big consequences:

        • ‘+2’ ceases to be an infinite series. if n is a number bigger than any human could compute, then there is nothing to determine what the correct application would be. more generally, standards of correct application extend no further than our finite capacity to apply the rule

        • there is no standard of correctness independent of the verdict we reach when we consider the question, so we must give up the intuitive idea that the truth/falsity of a sentence is determined by how the world is rather than what we judge when we consider the matter

    • Deflationism: whereas for the constructivist, Wittgenstein constructs something normative from something non-normative, for the deflationist he takes facts about rules and standards of correctness as basic and irreducible. Rules have the features we ordinarily think they have, so that ‘+2’ really is infinite

      • how we respond is not based on a natural way of going on (constuctivism), but a rule we are naturally disposed to follow when given e.g. the series ‘2, 4, 6, 8’

      • the correct continuation is not absolutely the simplest/most natural (Platonism) but the continuation we find simplest or most natural, which is a rule

      • deflationism appeals to how we usually understand rules, and how we explain correct applications to deviant pupils - we take the meaning of the rule for granted

  • Platonism and constructivism both think that philosophy can give a more informative answer to the question ‘what makes this the correct continuation?’ - they think that there is an external point of view that we can adopt, whether the nature of numbers/colours (Platonism) or our nature (constructivism)

    • for the...

Buy the full version of these notes or essay plans and more in our Wittgenstein Notes.