This website uses cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. Learn more

Law Notes Jurisprudence Notes

Obligation To Obey Notes

Updated Obligation To Obey Notes

Jurisprudence Notes

Jurisprudence

Approximately 417 pages

Jurisprudence notes fully updated for recent exams at Oxford and Cambridge. These notes cover all the LLB core jurisprudence readings from Hart to Dworkin to Raz to Mill and Kelsen and much much more. These notes are perfect for anyone studying either law or the philosophy of law, no matter where they are based.

These notes are formed from readings of the primary texts (i.e. the original books) and academic papers, then condensed down as much as possible. Everything is split up by topic and y...

The following is a more accessible plain text extract of the PDF sample above, taken from our Jurisprudence Notes. Due to the challenges of extracting text from PDFs, it will have odd formatting:

Obligation to Obey

NB: ‘GD’ = ‘Great Debates’ by McBride and Steel

The ‘obligation to obey’ refers to a prima facie, general, moral obligation to obey the law. This is an obligation to X because the law requires X.

Accounts of obligations:

  1. Austin/Kelsen: Sanction theories. What constitutes obligations is the social resources with which they are enforced. FAILS because does not account for sanction-less duties and the normative force of obligations.

  2. Hart: Rule-based theory. Sanctions might oblige people to conform, but people only have an obligation when subjected to a practiced social rule. FAILS because not all rules are backed up by social pressure. See Week 2 for Dworkin’s objections to the social rule thesis.

  3. Raz: Reason-based theory. What constitutes obligations is the kind of reasons for action they offer: by imposing obligations, authorities purport to offer protected reasons.

Non-voluntarist theories of obligation to obey:

  1. Dworkin: Associative obligations. Associative obligations arise in a true community (where there are special and individualised obligations based on a mutual and equal concern for each member of the community). Legal duties are forms of associative obligations. These associative obligations are what justifies official coercion.

    1. GD: These four conditions may be necessary but insufficient conditions for associative obligations, e.g. familial duties may exist because of the emotional ties between family members.

  2. Raz: Instrumental justification (NJT). Normal justification thesis: An authority is legitimate if a subject is more likely to better conform with the reasons that apply to him if he accepts the directives of the authority as authoritatively binding, rather than acting on his own judgments (ensuring conformity to right reason). This is the service conception of authority. This can be applied to governmental authority.

    1. A government has genuine legitimate authority if it claims to impose obligations on people by communicating an intention to do so and it succeeds in doing that (because there is a good moral case for it). Whether the subject complies is irrelevant to authority/legitimacy.

      1. NB: The NJT is a way for an authority to be legitimate. Thus, the government is not legitimate per se, but the government’s authority is legitimate. To Raz, ‘legitimate’ just means ‘justified’.

    2. Clear to see how the NJT justifies an authority, but what gives rise to an obligation to obey? Is it that as rational beings we have an obligation to act in accordance with reason?

  3. Anscombe: Necessity. The domain of authority is the domain of necessary social functions. These are goods which anyone would want and require social co-operation to produce.

    1. Green: Many of the activities of a legitimate government are optional (e.g. supporting education).

  4. Rawls: Duty to support just institutions. Not supporting just institutions would result in great harms to society. Waldron: If we lived in a state of nature, we would be in a state of peril. We thus have a natural duty to secure compliance with a set of rules which secure peace and protect basic moral rights.

    1. Simmons: Law does much more than prohibiting behaviour that would endanger people à the duty is too narrow.

      1. GD: Locality – we supposedly only have a duty to support the just institutions of the society in which we live – why not to support just institutions wherever they exist?

  5. Harm to society. Disobeying laws will set a ‘bad example’ and encourage people to disobey the law generally (this equally applies to unjust laws).

    1. E.g. judges still apply legal rules which are slightly unjust or else it undermines the effectiveness of governments.

    2. Raz: Some violations of law do not undermine the effectiveness of government or harm society (e.g. offences not known to anyone, violating the interests of one individual only).

    3. NB: The ‘harm to society’ and ‘duty to support just institutions’ arguments tend to overlap.

Voluntarist theories of obligation to obey:

  1. Consent. Subjects of a legal system consent to their being governed.

    1. Most people cannot be said to have expressed their consent. Continued residence is not tacit consent to obey (some people do not have the means to leave).

    2. Steel: Consent is permissive in character, whereas promising is generative (about creating obligations) à consent does not create obligations. Consent theory is actually about promising, and there are limits to the power to bind oneself, e.g. a person cannot bind themselves to become a slave.

      1. Q: Does the power to promise include the power to bind oneself to do unjust things? If not, then this theory only allows for obligations to obey perfectly just laws.

  2. Raz: Expressive obligations / “respect for law”

    1. One can acquire an obligation to obey the laws of his community by “identifying with or belonging to the community”, acquiring a “respect for law”. This “respect for law” grounds a quasi-voluntary obligation to obey the law: quasi-voluntary because there is no “moral duty to feel a sense of belonging in a community”. Since it is quasi-voluntary, though, it cannot be said that everyone has an obligation to obey the law.

      1. GD: This conception of ‘respect for law’ is too restrictive. Loyalty to one’s friend may extend to performing minor wrongs because they ask you, but there are limits à ‘respect for law’ may not give rise to obligations when laws are very unjust.

  3. Rawls: Fair play. Those who accept the benefits of fair scheme of cooperation have a duty to do their allotted part under that scheme.

    1. Nozick: The mere fact that you have received those benefits cannot oblige you, even if you welcome those benefits (think of his public entertainment centre example).

      1. BUT: It can be said that because you need the benefits that the legal system gives you, you implicitly asked for them. Two rebuttals:

        1. Legal systems provide benefits that are much more than those necessary to well-being.

        2. A person might wish to obtain that benefit...

Buy the full version of these notes or essay plans and more in our Jurisprudence Notes.